Garfunkel Defends His Art
In the Apology, Plato has Socrates offer the following dim report of his encounter with the poets:
"I am almost ashamed to speak of this, but still I must say that there is hardly a person present who would not have talked better about their poetry than they did themselves. That showed me in an instant that not by wisdom do poets write poetry, but by a sort of genius and inspiration; they are like diviners or soothsayers who also say many fine things, but do not understand the meaning of them."
This brief interview (see link above) with Art Garfunkel presents a nice challenge to the suggestion that artists are unlikely to comprehend--let alone articulate--the meaning of their art. Of course, Simon was arguably the poet behind Garfunkel's most famous work. But it hardly makes Garfunkel's insights less impressive to note that he was the voice, not the wordsmith.
Part of what is nice about the interview is that it belongs to a genre we are seeing more of these days: the reconciliation story of parties to a once-acrimonious musical divorce, who have gained the maturity that sometimes comes with age. But beyond this sentimental comfort, we find some genuinely reflective insights.
Consider, for instance, Garfunkel's description of the power of collaborative friendship:
"How about the very mentality of Paul Simon? This is a very interesting Paul Simon with a mind that can reach into the future, and I am a spiritual partner. When you sing with a partner and he has a very pleasing sound, and he's your friend and you laugh a lot, you soon start making music with the heads very close to each other, the noses almost touching. And you study the diction, and you create over your two heads a little bubble of reality and sound. When I work with Paul, I go into that dome, that invisible, small circumference dome. And when you visit that place, it's apart from life on Earth, it's its own very pleasing soundscape."
One might have to go back to Montaigne to find a better description of the way that friendship, through intense intimacy that might appear small, can actually offer a magnanimous gift to the world.
In another link with Plato--here, the Plato of the Symposium--we find the suggestion that there is some relationship between eros (broadly understood), friendship, and beautiful productions: recording by oneself is not the same. "You miss the electricity that lights up the recording session and makes it all fun and games and makes the night go on for many extra hours because partnership is juicy."
Or how about this description of singing itself?
"To me, the act of singing is an expression of love. You form it in the vocal cords. When you love your song and you lose yourself into the song . . . it's very tough to analyze the act of singing."
Here we have intensely personal love giving rise to that unique overcoming of the person as self-consciousness: the song expresses the love, and the love allows oneself to let go of the self. And there is even a Socratic recognition that the topic is difficult to understand--worthy of contemplation, but resisting analysis.
But what struck me most about this conversation was Garfunkel's unabashed ambition for excellence--and for recognition of his excellence. He is not satisfied with being known as "the guy with the silver voice." He wants to be "a virtuoso singer," and to be seen as a virtuoso singer. And he wants people to remember that they were good--the "real thing"--that they "recorded as if a record was an important thing," a thing that, when done well, was a masterpiece. He wants, he says, "to be in that world of a real artist."
Perhaps this is also a challenge to a Platonic thought. One can glean from some of Plato's dialogues that, while one ought to strive for excellence, one should scorn the opinion of the masses who presume themselves to be good judges. This thought offers something important and useful. But how are we to inspire a generation to fight and claw for greatness, if we are ashamed to say that we want to be great ourselves? Garfunkel does not seem to desire recognition for the sake of the goodies it brings--fame, money, etc. He seems to desire it as a kind of assurance that he has achieved some of what he strives for. And that, I think, is an innocent and admirable desire.
Monday, September 3, 2012
Wednesday, July 11, 2012
What One Learns in loco parentis.
George Eliot’s Silas
Marner is in part the story of a broken man, repaired by love of a child.
From the moment that these two “lone things” find one another, the spidery
existence of the miser expands as she forces his vision out and forward, warms
“him into joy because she had joy.”
It is a beautiful story, though parts of it seem wildly
implausible to me. But I am interested in this benign portrait of a kind of
stepparent—a man who takes care of little Eppie simply because she is there,
and because they both need love. For Eppie and Silas, there are no “real”
parents in their story, at least not for quite a while. Yet Silas is still in
that odd boundary position that we stepparents know too well: loving without
the biological ground of love, without the recognition of bonds afforded to
other parents, and without the security of the indestructible love that most
children naturally feel for the parents they have known since birth.
Those of you who are parents of transitional children—those
strange beings on the cusp of adulthood that we too innocuously call
“teenagers”—may question that last part. Attempting to love these sometimes moody and narcissistic little beings can feel like a thankless, hopeless task. But—to
generalize irresponsibly from my own and a few other cases—I can say that these
little beings still love their parents, even as they are saying and doing
things that break the parents’ hearts. And there is even hope that they may
grow up, remember those ugly moments, and feel truly remorseful and grateful
that you put up with them nonetheless. The tragic case of abused children who
still cling to their abusive parents shows the power of this love. This is a
horrible basis for security, but I maintain that there is security there to be
had.
Such security is less available to a stepparent. Not only
must she fight against the lack of early bonding, she must also overcome a
cultural history full of stories of wicked stepparents, and perhaps the
hostility that often results from divorce and remarriage. She must love in full
knowledge that the love may never be returned. There is consolation in one’s
spouse of course—who, if he is worth loving, will love you all the more for
loving his children. Nonetheless, the stepparent’s love can never be rooted in
the promise of strict reciprocity.
And now that I have mentioned the difference, I wish to do
it away. The truth is that no parent’s love should be rooted in such a promise.
It simply is not good for the parent, who is in a position of greater strength
and therefore must exhibit greater magnanimity. We must love because we have
the strength to love, and because others have given us that strength through
their own love. This, I believe, is called grace.
So does this let those of us who were or are narcissistic
little beings off the hook? By no means. As I recall from somewhere, the proper
response to grace is unceasing gratitude. Expressing it is an excellent way to
enlarge one’s own soul, thus making future magnanimity possible. We were all
once lone things: if someone saved you from that, you owe them everything—at the
very least the acknowledgement of their gift.
Tuesday, May 1, 2012
On "spirit" and "spirituality"
One hears a lot of talk—a lot of loose talk—about the "spirit" and "spirituality." But such loose talk may be indispensable. Certainly it's preferable to one way of dismissing the spirit. This is the brutal attempt to reduce everything worth talking about to a mechanism. Such a reduction is tasteless, because (as Nietzsche says) it betrays the wish to “divest existence
of its rich ambiguity” (more
literally, “its multi-aspected character” [seines
vieldeutigen Charakters]). Nietzsche invites us to imagine
a critic who judges a piece of music according to how much of it can be
counted, calculated and expressed in formulas. What would such a critic grasp in the piece? “Nothing, really nothing of what is
‘music’ in it.” Similarly, those
who try to grasp a person purely in terms of mechanism will grasp an aspect, but
only an aspect, of the human
being. Like existence itself,
human beings are multi-aspected. If
the facets in human beings that do not reveal themselves to mechanistic analysis
are to be seen, we must continue to use categories that are not at home in materialistic
natural science. To suppose
otherwise—to think that everything “real” about human beings can be understood
mechanistically—is a “faith with which so many materialistic natural scientists
rest content nowadays.” To call it
a faith is not a compliment (at least, not from Nietzsche). The
faith’s directive to permit “counting, calculating, weighing, seeing, and
touching, and nothing more” is, Nietzsche says, “a crudity and naiveté,
assuming that it is not a sickness of the spirit, an idiocy” (Gay Science 373).
It is vital to see that Nietzsche has no interest
in making the world safe for the “materialistic natural scientist.” Equally important is to grasp that he
is not a dualist. We should
continue to speak of “spirit”—but not as though it names an entity that exists,
or can exist, apart from the body.
When Nietzsche speaks harshly of “spirit,” he means to criticize a
particular notion of “spirit.” He
means spirit conceived as disembodied, a ghostly thing that hovers above the body. For this idea of
spirit, Nietzsche has nothing but scorn. “Pure spirit is pure lie,” he says in one place. But spirit is not “pure spirit.” The despisers of the body speak of
“spirit.” They do not succeed in
speaking of spirit. What, then,
does Nietzsche understand by spirit?
If spirit is not to be confused with “pure spirit,” what is it?
To tackle this question swiftly, to quickly get
into it and then out again, one cannot do better than to examine two aphorisms,
both from the Gay Science. Aphorism 329 begins by noticing the
“breathless haste” with which Americans work. This haste, the “distinctive vice of the new world,” has
“begun to infect old Europe with its ferocity and is spreading a lack of
spirituality (Geistlosigkeit) like a
blanket. Even now one is ashamed
of resting, and prolonged reflection almost gives people a bad
conscience.” To rest and to
reflect are two activities proper to spirit. Rather than genuinely reflect on a
question, giving it as much time as it requires, “one thinks with a watch in one’s
hand.” Instead of resting with
companions over a well-prepared dinner, “one eats one’s midday meal while
reading the latest news of the stock market.” If one is drawn to these counterfeits of rest and reflection,
it is because “one lives as if one always ‘might miss out on something.’” Those dominated by such anxiety simply
have no time or energy “for ceremonies, for being obliging in an indirect way,
for esprit in conversation, and for
any otium at all.” Moreover, the time-crunched chase for
gain does not promote genuine virtue: “Virtue has come to consist of doing
something in less time than someone else.” Nor does it reward honesty: “hours in which honesty is permitted have become rare.” When efficiency trumps virtue and
honesty, the natural consequence is a deflation of the spirit, notwithstanding any corresponding inflation of bank accounts and multi-story houses. “Living in a constant chase after gain
compels people to expend their spirit to the point of exhaustion in continual
pretense and overreaching and anticipating others.” Such a life, while perhaps diverting, cannot be called
joyful. Those educated to excel in
the chase are becoming “increasingly suspicious of all joy! More and more, work enlists all good conscience on its side; the desire for joy
already calls itself a ‘need to recuperate’ and is beginning to be ashamed of
itself. ‘One owes it to one’s
health’—that is what people say when they are caught on an excursion in the
country.”
From Aphorism 329, one learns what Nietzsche
deems bad for the spirit, along with he takes to be good for it. Here's a quick table. On the left, the good; on the right, the bad.
Leisure Exhaustion
Reflection Thought
bound to a schedule
Ceremony Dismissal
of ritual as “pointless”
Indirect
helpfulness Restriction
to what is obviously of service
Conversational esprit Plain, witless speech
Conversational esprit Plain, witless speech
Honesty Pretense
Contentment Overreaching
and anticipating others (cf. pleonexia)
Desire
for joy Temporary
respite from weariness
Good
conscience about joy Bad
conscience about what is useless for gain
This table does not pretend to be exhaustive. It could be expanded by analyzing other
aphorisms that use “spirit” as a key term. It suffices, however, to show that when Nietzsche speaks of
“spirit,” he talks about nothing detached from the body. He intends, rather, to convey something
about the activities and qualities of embodied human beings. Those who despise the body, but claim
to value spiritual activities and qualities, can be reminded that we never do
encounter these activities and qualities in separation from bodies. Against the reductive mechanist or
materialist, we can observe that these qualities and activities are but minimally illuminated by approaches that reduce body to what can counted,
calculated and expressed in formulas.
Nietzsche picks up the intrinsic connection
between the spirit and joy in Aphorism 359. “There is a human being who has turned out badly, who does
not have enough spirit to be able to enjoy it but just enough education to realize
this.” Such a human being, who is
“fundamentally ashamed of his existence,” is joyless and therefore less
spiritual than his joyful counterpart with a good conscience. He will at some point seek “revenge
against the spirit.” He will seek
“to give himself in his own eyes the appearance of superiority over more
spiritual people and to attain the pleasure of an accomplished revenge at least in his imagination.” By what means? By morality—not higher morality, but
exploitation of the “big moral words.”
Nietzsche lists “justice, wisdom, holiness, virtue." To this list, we can and should add “spirituality.” Those who love
to describe themselves as “spiritual” tend to have little of what Nietzsche
would regard as genuine spirit.
More likely they are “born enemies of the spirit”; they fear genuine
spirit and seek to revenge themselves against it. Even philosophers are subject to this harsh judgment. It applies particularly to the kind
of philosopher who continually speaks about “wisdom.” To talk about wisdom about the time will perhaps impress
the inexperienced as “spiritual.”
The more experienced, however, will not be misled. All too often, the rhetoric of wisdom functions
as a kind of screen. It is a “screen behind which the philosopher
saves himself because he has become weary, old, cold, hard.”
The aphorism concludes with a question:
“Wisdom as a screen behind which the philosopher hides from—spirit?” This ending strikes me as brilliant. It suggests what I've discovered from my own experience. The very people who are quickest to
attribute spirituality to themselves, who most pride themselves on
spirituality, are actually the least
spiritual, at least in any sense that counts.
Or it seems to me at the moment. I'm in the middle of working on a chapter, and I would love to hear your criticisms and insights.
Friday, April 20, 2012
The Psychology of Conviction
"What's wrong with our politicians
these days," one hears often, "is that they have no convictions."
This familiar complaint gets at a real problem. So many
politicians are unprincipled, in the sense that what drives them is exclusively
their own short-term interest. They will say anything to get
elected, no matter how outrageous, or how little they believe it themselves. We
can and should detest this.
We should not, however, let our justified
indignation mislead us into thinking that we simply want politicians who are
"principled." Why not? It's easy to think of people who
are sincere and "principled" in a sense, but who hold utterly wacky
views, and refuse to subject these views to examination and evidence. Such
types might in fact be more dangerous than their unprincipled
counterparts.
"After all, it is putting a very high
price on one's conjectures to have a man roasted alive because of them." This
line from Montaigne should not be forgotten. Nor should these ironic
words from C.G. Jung: "Even the holy Christian church, which is the
incarnation of divine love, burnt more than a hundred thousand of her own
children alive." There is little or nothing admirable about the
mere fact of having convictions. The problem with Anders Breivik is not
that he has no convictions. It is not that he is unprincipled or
insincere. Nor is it that he is insane, in the clinical sense (if there
is such a thing). That's an extreme example, but it illustrates the point
well.
Nietzsche speaks to the issue: “This is our
conviction: we confess it before all the world, we live and die for it. Respect
for all who have convictions! I have heard that sort of thing even out of
the mouths of anti-Semites. On the contrary, gentlemen! An
anti-Semite certainly is not any more decent because he lies as a matter of
principle." One might take Nietzsche's point to be that content is
more important than sincerity. Someone who does something good, whether
on principle or out of expediency, is preferable to someone who does something
wicked but on principle. Sincerity, if it is a virtue at all, is not the
highest virtue. Insincerity, though almost certainly a vice, is yet not
the worst vice.
Nietzsche’s emphasis, however, is a little
different. He seems to think that one can be fully sincere, fully
convinced or “convicted” (as some like to say), and yet fundamentally
dishonest. For Nietzsche, honesty is not really a function of subjective
sincerity. It has to do, rather, with one’s willingness to resist not
only deceiving, but also being deceived. Positively, it requires
one to continually ask hard questions and to subject one’s answer to those
questions (and indeed, one’s formulation of the questions themselves) to the
most probing tests. No matter how sincere the anti-Semite is in holding
his anti-Semitism, he is guilty of a fundamental kind of dishonesty, because he
is lazy with himself. He is willing to deceive and to be deceived. He
holds anti-Semitism out of conviction, but not out of intellectual
honesty.
What's the alternative? Something
like this: views based on an examination of things which proceeds according to
what Nietzsche calls the “intellectual conscience.” (See the second
aphorism of the Gay Science.)
Nietzsche combines an attack on the “psychology of conviction” with a
strong affirmation of the intellectual conscience and its attendant virtue,
honesty or probity (Redlichkeit) That alone prevents him, I
think, from approving of politicians who are simply unprincipled. It also
enables him to distinguish between the ersatz honesty of subjective sincerity
and the genuine article.
Monday, April 16, 2012
Should we chase superstition and fear from our hearts?
"We should chase superstition and fear from our hearts, if we're going to survive and take levels of sanity higher." This won't win any prizes for beautiful poetry, though it does scan perfectly well when sung by Andy Partridge. At any rate, as I was listening to "Merely a Man" the other day (it appears on XTC's 1989 double-LP Orange and Lemons), I started to think less about the music (not their best, not their worst) and more about the sentiment expressed.
These questions took hold of me and refused to let go: Why does this sentiment seem particularly associated with self-proclaimed atheists and "free-thinkers"? Why do we so rarely hear it expressed by the self-identified religious?
These questions took hold of me and refused to let go: Why does this sentiment seem particularly associated with self-proclaimed atheists and "free-thinkers"? Why do we so rarely hear it expressed by the self-identified religious?
One possible answer: Religious folks share the sentiment, but simply don't think it gets at a serious problem. While superstition and fear are not good things, godlessness and atheism are much worse. We don't need to worry too much about the superstitious and fearful. We can assume they're OK, as long as they're saying their prayers, receiving the sacraments, or whatever. Even those who have a bad diet overall simply can't help but provide themselves with the nutrition they need for the general well-being of their organism. Superstition and fear, while not exactly praiseworthy things, pose no real threat to spiritual well-being. The intellectual conscience is fine for those who want it. But ultimately, it's optional. It's not integral to piety.
This answer strikes me as hard to defend. Consider the analogy to bodily health just invoked. To slowly poison yourself through bad food and drink means that you will not feel as good as you should feel. It entails that you will probably die an earlier death than you would like. In matters of the spirit, things are much worse. Any approach to God infected by superstition is likely to be a form of idolatry. It will cause one to miss the mark altogether.
Some penetrating religious observers see the point. Pascal, for one, insists that genuine piety is different from superstition. He notices that there are many who claim to believe, but do so out of superstition. Indeed, he does not merely notice this, but uses it to support his claim that "there are few true Christians." Or, as Nietzsche says in one place, in every religion the religious person is an exception.
So Pascal and Partridge agree (if only on this): we should chase superstition from our hearts. But my original questions seem to re-emerge: why do religious folk seem generally not to be inspired by the sentiment? Why do we so rarely hear it coming from them? Why might an impartial observer conclude that those who concern themselves with superstition and fear as problems are more likely to be anti-religious than religious?
A second, darker answer suggests itself. Many religious folk have a bad conscience about the whole matter. In their quiet moments, they suspect that their own faith adds up to little more than fear and superstition. The cry to "chase superstition and fear from our hearts" does not resonate, because it would mean to empty their own hearts. Easier to go after other people, rather than worry about one's own darkness.
Is this answer correct? I don't know. Perhaps it applies to all of us some of the time, and some of us all of the time.
Here's a third possible answer (really a variant of the first): smart religious folk don't think too much these days about superstition, because they see that the alleged imperative to rid ourselves of superstition and fear is a bit old-fashioned. However worked up those quaint Enlightenment folks might have been, we occupy a different historical moment. For the most part, we've managed to let go of the worst superstitions, including the superstition that reasoned opposition to superstition will produce a more humane society. As for the superstitions that remain, what harm do they do? It's nice to have a bit of enchantment in our lives. The real threat to our humanity, in any case, does not come not from the superstitious. It arises from those who would mercilessly debunk anything and everything.
Here's a third possible answer (really a variant of the first): smart religious folk don't think too much these days about superstition, because they see that the alleged imperative to rid ourselves of superstition and fear is a bit old-fashioned. However worked up those quaint Enlightenment folks might have been, we occupy a different historical moment. For the most part, we've managed to let go of the worst superstitions, including the superstition that reasoned opposition to superstition will produce a more humane society. As for the superstitions that remain, what harm do they do? It's nice to have a bit of enchantment in our lives. The real threat to our humanity, in any case, does not come not from the superstitious. It arises from those who would mercilessly debunk anything and everything.
The last strand of this answer derives from a certain reading of C.S. Lewis's The Abolition of Man. Lewis is right, I think, to take aim at a certain kind of "debunker" who, whatever his intention, does not exactly succeed in producing better thinkers or better human beings. Moreover, when Lewis calls for the "irrigation of deserts" against the tendency of the debunkers, he does not mean to suggest that deserts should be watered by superstition. I can follow Lewis a good way down this path. Nonetheless, the sense that in our present times, credulity and superstition are not much of a problem strikes me as mostly an error. We have little interest in chasing superstition and fear from our hearts. But is it really because there is nothing to chase away?
I don't pretend to have exhausted the possibilities. I'm still wondering. Feel free to wonder with me in the comments...
Tuesday, February 28, 2012
Snobbery and Playing God
Rick Santorum has accused Obama of snobbery for wanting every American to go to college. Much of the negative response concerns his rhetoric. The governor of my home state reflected the general mood with his "I wish he'd said it differently."
Perhaps, but I'm more interested in asking about the matter than the manner of what he said. Is it snobbish to want everyone to go to college?
Obama's plan for universal higher education would have been unthinkable in past centuries--for many reasons. Among those reasons was the widespread belief that not everyone belonged in the university, because it was in people's best interest not to quit the sphere into which they were born. Pretending that this system promoted a separate-but-equal system would be the height of bad faith, as separate-but-equal claims generally are. If any views about higher education qualify as snobbish, this one certainly does.
For the most part, such views are--thankfully--no longer live options. But how could their apparent opposite--the idea that everyone belongs in college--then be snobbish?
Because the truth of the matter is that some people go to college and some do not, and the desire for everyone to do so seems to imply that the first group, at least at the completion of their formal education, is somehow better or better off than the second.
By some standards--particularly those that are easy to measure--it is clear that college graduates are better off. Their lifetime earning is higher; their rate of unemployment is lower. Because these goods appeal to everyone, their value is difficult to question. But we do run into dangerous territory if we mean that college graduates are morally better, more excellent human beings, or members of a higher class defined by something other than earning potential.
Obama attempted to respond to this criticism by insisting that he did not mean that everyone needs a four-year degree. He intended his remarks to apply to technical training as well--the kind that might help those "decent men and women who go out and work hard every day," in Santorum's words, earn and keep gainful employment. He did not mean, in other words, that everyone needs the traditional liberal education associated with the four-year degree and that earlier, snobbish class system.
Fortunately, one is increasingly unlikely to acquire a liberal education at most four-year colleges.
It is worth asking, however, what such an education might liberate one from. At its best, it might liberate one from the kind of sentiment expressed in Santorum's following sentences, much neglected by the news reports:
"Oh, I understand why he wants you to go to college. He wants to remake you in his image. I want to create jobs so people can remake their children into their image, not his."
This religious allusion is particularly odd. If we are already made in God's image, as I presume Santorum believes, do we need remaking in the image of fallen human beings instead? Putting that aside, ought parents to see their goal as reproducing images of themselves? Isn't the more loving and properly humble thing to hope and strive that your children might overcome your weaknesses, escape your faults, and excel your achievements?
Certainly, it is frightening to allow one's children to learn. Hoping for and encouraging their education raises the very real possibility that they may come to believe and embrace things that are foreign or even anathema to their parents.
There is nothing wrong with wanting your children to share your standards and convictions. There is something wrong with prioritizing sameness in itself over their development, or with closing oneself off to the possibility that they might grow to teach you that your standards and convictions are misguided. There is something more wrong about resenting your children if they choose to follow those standards in ways that you did not. The child of a lawyer may choose to pursue justice by living with the poor, and the child of a steel worker may choose to mold the world through the quite different honest hard work of a heart surgeon. Neither child would be the image of the parents. But if either parent responded to this situation by resenting her child's choices, the accusation of snobbery would be apt indeed.
One does not, indeed, need a formal education to come to these insights about human development. My father, who does not have a four-year degree, possesses them to the highest degree of anyone I have ever known. But again, liberal education at its best makes such insights available to some not so parentally blessed. Can everyone benefit from such an education? Is everyone capable of it?
This is a genuinely difficult question. I can only respond with the remark of one of my students on this topic:
"We have to hope so."
Wednesday, February 22, 2012
On Lenten Observance and the Labyrinth of the Heart
In Nietzsche's too-neglected essay, "Schopenhauer as Educator," he observes that "wherever there has been tyranny, there the solitary philosopher has been hated; for philosophy offers an asylum to a man into which no tyranny can force its way, the inward cave, the labyrinth of the heart."
This is a mournful, beautiful sentiment. Here is a man who knows that philosophy can indeed console--and a man whose forced solitude has often made consolation necessary.
It is, perhaps ironically, a sentiment appropriate for Ash Wednesday. Christ offers us the deepest consolation--a joy that can only be had after the cutting engagement with sin. And, at its best, the church provides the means for such consolation--forms and rituals that help bring our hearts, minds, and bodies into the necessary receptive stance.
I grew up in the Baptist church, and there are many things about that formation for which I will always be grateful. But my worship experience as a child lacked a deep sense of such rituals. And it lacked altogether a sense of the liturgical year beyond Christmas and Easter. Advent was a children's game involving calendars and festivity, and Lent was missing entirely.
Like many with this formation, I have treasured coming to know more liturgical traditions. The liturgy, at its best, provides words when words fail us. It is a sanctuary in the true sense--an asylum into which tyranny cannot force its way.
At its best. But it is all too easy to forget--perhaps because it seems so obvious--that forms can also be empty shells. Worse still, they can be sources of pride, thus contradicting everything this day is supposed to remind us of. Those of us walking around with ashes on our foreheads must ask ourselves: is this really humbling, or do I want people to know that I have observed the appropriate ritual today?
The form, the asylum, the sanctuary are all open spaces with walls--or perhaps cradles--around them. They are nothing unless filled with the inwardness of the labyrinthine hearts who realize how much they need them.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)